
Understanding Utility Theories and Decision Making
Explore the concept of utility theories, different types of utility theories, decision-making based on expected value, challenges with expected value, and the application of expected utility models in decision-making scenarios. Learn how to derive utility functions and make optimal choices based on expected outcomes.
Download Presentation

Please find below an Image/Link to download the presentation.
The content on the website is provided AS IS for your information and personal use only. It may not be sold, licensed, or shared on other websites without obtaining consent from the author. If you encounter any issues during the download, it is possible that the publisher has removed the file from their server.
You are allowed to download the files provided on this website for personal or commercial use, subject to the condition that they are used lawfully. All files are the property of their respective owners.
The content on the website is provided AS IS for your information and personal use only. It may not be sold, licensed, or shared on other websites without obtaining consent from the author.
E N D
Presentation Transcript
Types of utility theories Six Types Single Attribute Multiple Attribute Riskless No conflict Multi-attribute Utility Risky Expected Utility Multi-att Exp Utility Uncertain Subj Exp Util Multi-Subj-Exp-Ut
Example 1: Risky Single-Attribute (Years of Survival) Treatment State A (.2) State B (.3) State C (.5) X 40 30 20 Y 10 45 20 Expected Value Rule for choosing between Risky Actions Choose the Course of action with the largest expected payoff in the long run Using Example 1: EV(X) = (.2)(40) + (.3)(30) + (.5)(20) = 27.0 expected life years EV(Y) = (.2)(10) + (.3)(45) + (.5)(20) = 25.5 expected life years Choose X
Problems with Expected Value Knee Treatment State A (.9) State B (.1) Surgery 0 years of waiting 50 years of waiting Physical Therapy 7 years of waiting 5 years of waiting Example 2: Years required to wait for recovery EV(Surgery) = (.9)( 0 years) + (.1)(-50 years) = -5.0 years EV(Therapy) = (.9)(-7 years) + (.1)( -5 years ) = -6.8 years But perhaps you don't want to take the Chance? The utility of living X years may be nonlinear For example, the increase from 0 to 10 years of waiting may be more painful than the increase from 40 to 50 years of waiting.
Expected Utility Model for Ex. 2: Choose the maximum expected utility: EU(Surgery) = (.9)u(0 years) + (.1)u(50 years) EU(Therapy) = (.9)u( 7 years) + (.1)u(5 years) How to Find the utility function u( x years) ? 0, 5, 7, 50 years
Step 1: u(worst outcome) = u(50 years of waiting) = 0 u(best outcome) = u(0 years of waiting) = 1
Step 2: P 1-p A 0 years (best) 50 years (worst) B x years x years Solve the following indifference relation: Find the probability p that makes you indifferent between: A) p chance to receive the best outcome, (1-p) chance to receive the worst outcome B) Receive x for sure.
Step 3: Set u(x) = p found in Step 2. Why? Setting u(0)=1 (best), u(50) =0 (worst) u(A)=p u(0)+(1-p)u(50) = p 1+(1-p)0 = p = u(B) = u(x)
E.g., to find the Utility of 7 years relative to the best (0 years) and worst (50 years): Find the probability p that makes you indifferent between: A. p chance to receive 0 years, (1-p) chance to receive 50 years. B. Receive 7 for sure. Suppose p = .95 makes you indifferent, then u( 7 years ) = .95.
And to find the Utility of 5 years relative to the best (0 years) and worst (50 years): Find the probability p that makes you indifferent between A. p chance to receive 0 years, (1-p) chance to receive 50 years. B. Receive 5 for sure. Suppose p = .98 makes you indifferent, then u( 5 years ) = .98
Substituting these utilities EU(Surgery) = (.9)u(0) + (.1)u(50) = (.9)(1.0) + (.1)(0) = .900 EU(Therapy) = (.9)u(7) + (.1)u(5) = (.9)(.95)+(.1)(.98) = .953
Ex 3: Decision Under Uncertainty Enemy Present Hit Miss Enemy Not Present False Alarm Correct Rejection Attack Do not Attack Little information available about location of enemy P(Enemy present) is deeply uncertain and people have widely different opinions Must rely on subjective probability judgments
Subjective Expected Utility (Savage 1954) SEU(Action) = s(Event1) u(action|E1) + s(Event2) u(action|E2) + s(Event3) u(action|E3) Additive Subjective Probabilities: If E1 and E2 are mutually exclusive then s(E1 Or E2) = s(E1) +s(E2)
Example 4: Riskless Multi-Attribute Used Car Option Cost Milage Ford 10,000 dollars 60,000 miles Honda 12,000 55,000 Saturn 9,000 75,000 Toyota 11,000 55,000
Multi-Attribute Weighted Additive Rule Choose the alternative with the largest weighted additive value: MAU = w1a1+w2a2 Set w1 = 1, solve for w2 = w w = exchange rate for changing miles into dollars How to find the exchange rate?
Exchange Rate $ 12,000 55,000 miles $ 9,000 X miles Find the mileage X that make you indifferent between: A. A car with $12,000 cost and 55,000 miles B. A car with $9,000 cost and X miles. w = [ ($12,000) - ($9,000) ] / [ X - 55 miles ] Suppose X = 73,000 miles, then w = .167 dollar / mile
MAUT choice w = .167 dollar per mile V(F) = -$10,000 - (.167 dollar/mile)(60,000 mile) = -$20,020 V(H) = -$12,000 - (.167 dollar/mile)(55,000 mile) = -$21,185 V(S) = -$9,000 - (.167 dollar/mile)(75,000 mile) = -$21,525 V(T) = -$11,000 - (.167 dollar/mile)(55, 000 mile) = -$20,185 Choose Ford
Multiplicative: Value of Treatment = (Quality of Life) x (Duration of Life) Value of Investment = (Amount of Return)/(Delay of Return)
Averaging E.g., Grad Applicant Rating = [w1 GRE + w2 GPA + w3 Letters] / (w1+w2+w3) The averaging model produces a dilution effect: Mixing moderately good letters with very strong GRE and GPA only weakens the rating.
Principles of Rational Decision Making Von Neumann & Morgentstern (1947) Expected Utility Savage (1954) Subjective Expected Utility Keeney & Raiffa (1976) Multiattribute Utility
1.Transitivity If A > B and B > C then A > C 2.Dominance If A >= B on each attribute, then A >= B. 3.Independence If (A or X) > (B or X) then (A or Y) > (B or Y)
4.Sure Thing Principle If A > B under state of the world X and if A > B under state of the world (not X) then A > B when X is unknown 5.Substitutability If A = X and A > B then X > B.
6.Reduction to final outcomes Any complex multistage decision tree can be reduced to a simpler tree that has only the final outcomes and the final probabilities for each action. 7.Solvability If A > B > C then there is some p such (win A with p, otherwise C) = B 8.Dynamic Consistency follow through on plans
How does EU follow from these axioms? Assume A > B > C > D > E are certain payoffs (e.g life years) Set u(A) = 1, u(E) = 0
1. Assuming Final outcomes, a decision tree can be displayed as p A X q C r E D1 s B Y D t
Using Solvability we assume that solve for b, c, d that makes you indifferent A = (win A with probability a, otherwise E) a = 1 B = (win A with probability b, otherwise E) C = (win A with probability c, otherwise E) D = (win A with probability d, otherwise E) E = (win A with probability e, otherwise E) e = 0
Assuming substitutability we can replace D1 with D2 a 1 p 0 c X q 1 0 r e 1 0 D2 b a 1 s a 0 Y d 1 t 0
Assuming reduction to final outcomes p a + q c + r e X 1 0 D3 s b + t d Y 1 0
Now assuming dominance we choose the branch with the higher expected utility EU(X) = p a + q c + r e = p u(A) + q u(C) + r u(E) EU(Y) = s b + t d = s u(B) + t u(D)
Summary of Utility Models EV = p1 x1+ p2 x2+ p3 x3 EU = p1 u(x1)+ p2 u(x2)+ p3 u(x3) SEU = s(E1) u(x1)+ s(E2) u(x2)+ s(E3) u(x3) WADD = w1 v(x1)+w2 v(x2)+w3 v(x3) DD = w(t1) v(x1)+w(t2) v(x2)+w(t3) v(x3)